TY - GEN A1 - Aguado, Felicidad A1 - Cabalar, Pedro A1 - Fandinno, Jorge A1 - Pearce, David A1 - Perez, Gilberto A1 - Vidal, Concepcion T1 - Revisiting explicit negation in answer set programming T2 - Postprints der Universität Potsdam : Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Reihe N2 - A common feature in Answer Set Programming is the use of a second negation, stronger than default negation and sometimes called explicit, strong or classical negation. This explicit negation is normally used in front of atoms, rather than allowing its use as a regular operator. In this paper we consider the arbitrary combination of explicit negation with nested expressions, as those defined by Lifschitz, Tang and Turner. We extend the concept of reduct for this new syntax and then prove that it can be captured by an extension of Equilibrium Logic with this second negation. We study some properties of this variant and compare to the already known combination of Equilibrium Logic with Nelson's strong negation. T3 - Zweitveröffentlichungen der Universität Potsdam : Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Reihe - 1104 KW - Answer Set Programming KW - non-monotonic reasoning KW - Equilibrium logic KW - explicit negation Y1 - 2021 U6 - http://nbn-resolving.de/urn/resolver.pl?urn:nbn:de:kobv:517-opus4-469697 SN - 1866-8372 IS - 1104 SP - 908 EP - 924 ER - TY - JOUR A1 - Cabalar, Pedro A1 - Fandinno, Jorge A1 - Garea, Javier A1 - Romero, Javier A1 - Schaub, Torsten H. T1 - Eclingo BT - a solver for epistemic logic programs JF - Theory and practice of logic programming N2 - We describe eclingo, a solver for epistemic logic programs under Gelfond 1991 semantics built upon the Answer Set Programming system clingo. The input language of eclingo uses the syntax extension capabilities of clingo to define subjective literals that, as usual in epistemic logic programs, allow for checking the truth of a regular literal in all or in some of the answer sets of a program. The eclingo solving process follows a guess and check strategy. It first generates potential truth values for subjective literals and, in a second step, it checks the obtained result with respect to the cautious and brave consequences of the program. This process is implemented using the multi-shot functionalities of clingo. We have also implemented some optimisations, aiming at reducing the search space and, therefore, increasing eclingo 's efficiency in some scenarios. Finally, we compare the efficiency of eclingo with two state-of-the-art solvers for epistemic logic programs on a pair of benchmark scenarios and show that eclingo generally outperforms their obtained results. KW - Answer Set Programming KW - Epistemic Logic Programs KW - Non-Monotonic KW - Reasoning KW - Conformant Planning Y1 - 2020 U6 - https://doi.org/10.1017/S1471068420000228 SN - 1471-0684 SN - 1475-3081 VL - 20 IS - 6 SP - 834 EP - 847 PB - Cambridge Univ. Press CY - New York ER - TY - JOUR A1 - Cabalar, Pedro A1 - Fandinno, Jorge A1 - Schaub, Torsten H. A1 - Schellhorn, Sebastian T1 - Gelfond-Zhang aggregates as propositional formulas JF - Artificial intelligence N2 - Answer Set Programming (ASP) has become a popular and widespread paradigm for practical Knowledge Representation thanks to its expressiveness and the available enhancements of its input language. One of such enhancements is the use of aggregates, for which different semantic proposals have been made. In this paper, we show that any ASP aggregate interpreted under Gelfond and Zhang's (GZ) semantics can be replaced (under strong equivalence) by a propositional formula. Restricted to the original GZ syntax, the resulting formula is reducible to a disjunction of conjunctions of literals but the formulation is still applicable even when the syntax is extended to allow for arbitrary formulas (including nested aggregates) in the condition. Once GZ-aggregates are represented as formulas, we establish a formal comparison (in terms of the logic of Here-and-There) to Ferraris' (F) aggregates, which are defined by a different formula translation involving nested implications. In particular, we prove that if we replace an F-aggregate by a GZ-aggregate in a rule head, we do not lose answer sets (although more can be gained). This extends the previously known result that the opposite happens in rule bodies, i.e., replacing a GZ-aggregate by an F-aggregate in the body may yield more answer sets. Finally, we characterize a class of aggregates for which GZ- and F-semantics coincide. KW - Aggregates KW - Answer Set Programming Y1 - 2019 U6 - https://doi.org/10.1016/j.artint.2018.10.007 SN - 0004-3702 SN - 1872-7921 VL - 274 SP - 26 EP - 43 PB - Elsevier CY - Amsterdam ER -